Thursday, October 15, 2020

Moral Imagination and Literature: an Introduction to Ethical Criticism- Liyanage Amarakeerthi

 



(The text of a speech delivered at Annual General meeting of the Society for the Integration of Science and Human Values, (SISHVA) of the Department of Pali and Buddhist Studies, University of Peradeniya, on August 28,th  2018)  

 For a long time, SISHVA has been inviting me to give a talk, but I could not make myself available mainly because I was busy communicating with other audiences both in speech and writing. This time, however, I made special efforts to commit myself to doing this.

   Even today, I begin by breaking a promise because I have changed my topic a bit- so much for human values! I will not be talking about the debate between morality and aesthetics. After I started writing this talk on that topic, I felt bored since I have recently dealt with that issue in a book I translated early this year. In that book, Arts and the Man, Irwin Edman, the author talks about moralistic displeasure at art in following words: “Christian moralists realized how closely the senses are overlaid with a veil of sexual feeling. To become sensuously alive was to be also, if only incipiently or subconsciously, sexually awakened. Much of that glamorous intensity which goes with aesthetic experience is undoubtedly sexual in some its elements.”(46) Ultimate effect of aesthetics, which appeals to human senses, is bodily arousal that moralists aim to keep suppressed or at least at bay. But modern humans, Edman points out, are not afraid of sexuality and awakened senses. Freudians would argue that aesthetic beauty is the sublimated products of sexual energies that make moralists tremble in fear. If had stuck with that topic, I would have end somewhere there. But I hope I have better things to say.

      I do have my own affinities with the kind of intellectual climate SHISVA is trying to create in and around our University. For one thing, SHISVA’s efforts to get natural sciences and the Humanities into a conversion have a long history, and, perhaps, that is the only effort of that nature among us. In my recent writings, I myself have argued in numerous places that we compartmentalize our children into subject streams such as science, commerce, and arts too early in their lives. And even after entering the university, students of our faculty have no opportunities in their formal education to expose themselves to the basics of natural sciences, the philosophy of science, and history of science, and, the students at science-based faculties have almost no opportunities to develop their aesthetic sensibilities, critical thinking, philosophical reflection, moral imagination, ethical reasoning or, in general, to nurture the life of the mind. My translations of Martha Nussbaum’s Not for Profit: Why democracy needs the Humanities and Irwin Edman’s Arts and the Man and some of my own essays on the subject were almost only call in Sinhala language for holistic education within the intellectual scene in recent times. Here, I am joining you, quite happily and with a great deal of respect for you for keeping a conversation alive across faculties, disciplines, religions, and numerous other divides.  

Professor P.D. Premasiri suggested that I talk about something related to ethics, morality and literature. In our brief conversation about this occasion, he mentioned the long drawn confrontation between morality and aesthetics. “Moral person represented in literature” was suggested as another possible topic. In fact, they all are good topics that can be talked about in a manner that transcends all the divides I mentioned earlier. Ethics, in all possible nuances of the term, concerns all of us. Typically secular minded left thinkers also have recently paid considerable attention to “ethics”, “morality,” “moral leadership” and the like. Antonio Gramsci is particularly known for that. Marxist literary theorist Terry Eagleton wrote an entire chapter on “morality” in his influential book After Theory and claimed that contemporary cultural theorists cannot ignore the concept of morality, and, morality is not “moralism.” For him, to talk about ethics is to analyze the social structures within which human beings act and process their inner needs.   

In this talk, however, I am going to caste the net a bit wider: I want to say few things about the return of ethical criticism, and, the “currency” of morality in literary studies. Then, I will focus on a short story with which we can historicize ethical reasoning.

If one talked about “ethics” and “moral person” in relation to literature and art some twenty years ago, one could have been accused of being a naïve art lover because during those times poststructuralist thought had made it difficult to assign any ethical duty to language or texts. In that intellectual atmosphere, language and texts were understood to be unstable and slippery phenomena in which no authorial intention was possible. When one cannot mean anything stable in language and in texts, it is almost impossible to have any ethical intentions. Ethical intentions are NOT expected to be shaky and ambivalent.

If an author cannot ‘intend’ anything stable within a text, how can she or he make any ethical claim within it? A text, especially if it is a fairly rich literary text, would always have some groupings of signs that would rebel against ethical intentions of the author. The poststructuralist position against meaning was something like that.

  But when that period of high theory began to fade away, certain return of ethical criticism took place. Numerous theorists influenced by Aristotle, Kant, Wittgenstein began to show that language could still communicate. This time however, these claims about the things literature could do have been informed by a rich theoretical discourse on the limits of language. They seemed to ask something like this: “yes. Language is slippery, and it is difficult to harness language into a frame of authorial intentions, and intentions into texts where there are multiple competing meanings are at play. Can they still contribute to important social, political, ethical discourses in society?” To that question, resounding yes would be the answer by recent ethical critics. There are theorists and critics everywhere who still rejoice in almost narcissistic textual games with a sarcastic smile of superiority writ large on their faces. But the ethical imperatives in literature are regularly talked about now. And the fact that literature is an important mode of reflecting on the way we live is also emphasized often enough.  

   In addition, we have been talking about the representation of women, colonized people, ethnic minorities, sexual minorities, environmental degradation and so on all along while the theoretical discourse on the slipperiness of language was taking place. Arguably, ethical issues about those aspects have been raised even when ‘skepticism of language’ held the central stage of literary discourse. And as a writer, I never thought literature cannot contribute to socially significant discourses.

 In recent times, phrases such as ethics and literature, ethical criticism, moral imagination and so on are quite ubiquitous in the field of literary studies. Literary works, above all narrative arts, are often seen as sites for careful ethical reflection. This return of ethics surprises many who remember the beginning of classical thought on arts, especially Plato’s arguments. Let me quote from Tobin Siebers’s The Ethics of Criticism. In Plato’s eyes, poetry is savagely chaotic and a definite threat to the order of the republic. By encouraging acting, impersonation and pretense to science, it imperils the Delphic wisdom of knowing oneself. Literature entices citizens to play more than one role, destroying the possibility of justice. For Plato’s idea of justice depends on the neat perception that one person has one responsibility… Plato repeatedly described drama and poetry in terms of their ability to bring disorder into the order of the state.”(p. 19).  Plato is not alone in believing that human discourses should tame human beings into existing social structures such as state, culture, society, or social contracts. Platonic theory that requires the banishment of poet from the republic does not leave any room for articulating the ethical significance of literature. After all, a banished poet cannot contribute to the ethical make-up of the republic.

  But Plato did not have the last word on this matter. There is the other end of the spectrum. And at that end, we find Kant claiming that human beings are ends in themselves, as autonomous subjects, and they are not instruments of satisfying someone else’s personal desires. This is the “ethics of autonomy” - to borrow a phrase from Tobin Seibers(p. 44).  Even against the state or republic, a human being is an end in herself or himself. Philosopher of liberalism John Rawls echoes this Kantian position when he says, “Each person possesses an inviolability founded on justice that even the well-being of society as a whole cannot override (A Theory of Justice, p. 3).   

Martha Nussbaum

   In between Plato and Kant, there is Aristotle disagreeing with his teacher and re-conceptualizing the connection between literature and ethics. Some ethical theorists have attempted to turn Kantian idealism into a form of practical ethics coupling Kantian thought with Aristotelian ethics. Later in this talk, I will be talking about neo-Aristotelian philosopher Martha Nussbaum whose work I have found particularly useful in my activities of cultural criticism in Sri Lanka. Aristotle did not want to banish poets from the republic. “Literature, for Aristotle, reveals the instability of human existence and the difficulty of living morally in such a world. Aristotle’s approach was decidedly anti-Platonic, but his goals were not. Aristotle’s purpose was to discover a series of limits in order to guarantee the integrity of the city and to protect citizens from both outside and inside violence. That he refused, however, to banish literature, despite its apparently conflictual character, that he established literature as an instrument for judicial contemplation, opened the humanistic age of ethics, in which ethics advances toward the possibility of a political rather than a transcendental formationTragedy focuses on the political dimensions of ethics. It reveals that standards of justice are the products of political dimensions and not of ideal forms, thereby making it possible to debate those standards of justice.(Siebers. 22. My emphasis). 

   When participating in contemporary ethical discourses, Neo-Aristotelian thinkers focus on requirements for human flourishing within various forms of state and cultural structures rather than making absolute and transcendental ethical claims. That life is suffering is true in absolute terms; but if life is particularly suffering for the under-privileged, the poor, women, minorities, or the first year students of Sri Lankan universities, any ethical interventions on those matters need to be guided by secular and pragmatic conceptions of possibility of reform and individual and collective self-criticism. Without that, absolute terms such as life is suffering appear a detached and indifferent defense of the status quo.  

 In recent theorists of ethical criticism, I find a certain oscillation between Aristotelian and Kantian ethics, and one might be able to claim that it is a synthesis of the two. I am no philosopher to make a final conclusion of that matter. In practicing ethical criticism, I also freely draw on ideas put forward by both philosophers though I have special liking for Kant.

   An often misunderstood Kantian idea of ‘arts for art’s sake’, argues for an art not at the service of any mundane purpose. In that sense art is for non-utilitarian pleasure. As Siebers puts it, “The freer the work of art, the richer it is for taste. For Kant, “taste is the faculty of estimating an object or mode of representation by means of a delight or aversion apart from any interest. Literature excites the idea of a world free of interests, competition, and violence, and as such, it provides the image of the goal toward which ethics should strive (p. 24).

  Ethical implications of such a view need a bit of elaboration. If art exists as pure beauty without being an instrument of any purpose, even good purpose, that art signifies a world where human beings or things exist in total autonomy. No one is an instrument of someone else’s purpose or intent or pleasure. Things exist for themselves, and others learn to appreciate things for what they really are. To explain this, Nussbaum sites, in her Not for Profit, the well-known poem, “twinkle, twinkle little star, how I wonder what you are.” This little star is up above in the sky far away. But this insignificant distant star is personified; its identity is recognized; it is given agency for what it is. And the human child is trained to appreciate this distant star even though it is not practically or immediately useful to the child. The star is appreciated and celebrated for its mere existence not for its utilitarian significance in human affairs. For example, in this poem, the star is not valued for the possible guidance it may provide for travelers. Similarly, when we say,

.i j;=iqÿ

ù msßisÿ

fmdfydh ke;sÿ

is,a.;a n÷˜ in Sinhala we are appreciating the Wathusudu tree for the sake of its very existence. One can argue that, compared to the poem of the star, this poem is slightly utilitarian since to the narrator the tree is seen as having observed Buddhist precepts. Kantian idea “art for art’s sake” which outwardly looks totally apolitical    statement is deeply moral and therefore, political.

   “Kant differed from Plato in holding that the freedom of art no longer risks introducing chaos into the governing body, but instead designs the model for a world of free personalities, a republic of self-sufficient subjects purposively united. For Kant, art is the production of freedom by freedom, not the lie of inspired and insipid poets; it designs the ideal form of ethical practice. Most important, Kant’s idea of beauty cannot exist, as Plato’s and Aristotle’s can, within the totalitarian state” (Siebers. 24).

 

Cultivating Moral Imagination

As I said earlier Martha Nussbaum is a leading contemporary philosopher who argues that narrative art can cultivate moral imagination in readers. Her books, Fragility of Goodness (1986/2001), Love’s Knowledge(1992), Poetic Justice( 1997) Cultivating Humanity(1997), Political Emotions (2013) and so on, are well-known examples of her contribution to the field. Nussbaum’s work has not received equally by everyone in literary studies. For example, while appreciating her work on ethics and literature Robert Eaglestone in his book, Ethical Criticism: Reading After Lavinas, claims that Nussbaum was often reductive in her reading of literary texts (p. 45). In a way, what he is saying is that when teasing out ethical reasoning in a literary text one often ignores many other textual qualities in them. Nussbaum is aware of that almost unavoidable reductionism when her focus is not on celebrating formal literary merits. Writing a new preface to the fifteenth anniversary edition of Fragility of Goodness, Nussbaum says,

“…I still think that Aristotle's conception of the human being, and of practical deliberation, is of great importance for contemporary ethical and political thought; and I believe that the depiction of the plurality of goods and of conflicts among them that we find in both the poets and Aristotle offers insights that are absent from much of contemporary social reasoning (xv).”

And in Cultivating Humanity, she responds to possible accusations about reading literature in terms of ethical frameworks in them. “It is hard to justify such a claim without embracing an extreme kind of aesthetic formalism that is sterile and unappealing. The Western aesthetic tradition has had throughout its history an intense concern with character and community”(p.89).


Even though I have considerable training in much more complex modes of reading and analysis such as deconstruction, I find Nussbaum’s method quite useful in highlighting certain thematic issues about Sinhala literature. And her reductionism, if you want to call it that, stems largely from the nature of literary texts, which, by nature, have multiple meanings in them and dynamic formal arrangements. In contrast, ethical reasoning, by nature, has to be precise and definite. By making ethical claims based on literary texts, Nussbaum does not exhaust those texts so that they can no longer signify. No one can exhaust a good work of literature.

  Thus, for the rest of this talk I will stick with some key arguments of Nussbaum and to read a Sinhala short story in light of those arguments. Elaborating on how narrative art can cultivate “civic imagination” in readers, Nussbaum goes on to claim, “narrative art has the power to make us see the lives of the different with more than a casual tourist’s interest – with involvement and sympathetic understanding, with anger at our society’s refusals of visibility”(Cultivating Humanity. P. 88.). Here, she is referring to Ralph Ellison’s Invisible Man – a classic novel about how African Americans are not visible to the eyes of white people whose vision is shaped by racist ideologies early twentieth century America. Not only that these black subalterns cannot speak but also they are invisible. Any sensitive reader of Ellison’s novel is awakened to the fact that there are numerous invisibles all around us, and the novel is not only about racism in the US. Therefore, I think, Nussbaum is right in arguing that “narrative imagination is an essential preparation for moral interaction. Habits of empathy and conjecture conduce to a certain type of citizenship and a certain form of community: one that cultivates a sympathetic responsiveness to another’s needs, and understands the way circumstances shape those needs, while respecting separateness and privacy. This is so because of the way in which literary imagining both inspires intense concern with the fate of characters and defines those characters as containing inner life, not all of which is open to view; in the process the reader learns to have respect for the hidden contents of that inner world, seeing its importance in defining a creature as fully human (p.90. My Emphasis).

   Our everyday life does not always allow us to observe and reflect on the inner lives of our fellow human beings. As we discussed earlier, Ellison’s novel shows that many people are invisible to us even outwardly.

A moment of Redemption

      Let me rush into a wonderful short story by Kamal Perera, a leading fiction writer in Sinhala. The story, “Awasanayaka Arabuma” (or “the beginning of an ending”) is about a retired colonel, his dog, Rover, and his domestic servant, Selva. After the ending of the war in 2009, the colonel retires into his ancestral home located in a fairly large piece of land. He is alone. No information of his family life is given. With its many trees and bushes, the land is nearly a forest. Behind the house, he practices target shooting almost every day. He owns revolver. Rover, the dog is a large Rottweiler with whom the colonel goes hunting. When small animals such as rabbits are sho, the dog brings the dead animals to its master. In the process, the dog develops a taste for fresh blood and raw meat. One day, the colonel accidentally cuts his hand and the dog hanging around him licks the blood off the floor. The taste of human blood drives the dog insane, and one day, it jumps on to the colonel begins to rip the flesh off from all over him. When Selva the domestic servant hears the noise it is almost too late, he comes running to save the colonel. Until this moment in the story Selva was nearly invisible. The almost insane dog jumps onto Selva fatally wounding him in an instant. Meanwhile, the colonel manages to grab his revolver and shoots the dog to death. Selva, fatally wounded, is taken to hospital.
  Even though the war was over, the colonel was still living in a war-like situation, hunting, shooting and the like. He seems to be struggling with the traumas of war. Certain memories of war seem too hard to get rid of. But once Selva was injured, saving his life becomes the colonel’s moment of redemption, even of cleansing. There is immensely poignant moment in the story where the colonel washes blood off his body after coming back from the hospital. That moment of cleansing seems the ‘beginning of the ending’ for him.   

   The excellence of the story rests on the way it shows how the war-like structure of the colonel’s retirement does not allow him to gain a fresh view at life around him. And within that quasi-military structure and ideologies of heroism, he does not get to see Selva as a human being. Early in the story, his hunting buddy, Rover is presented as almost human, and its inner world is visible to the colonel and to us. Selva, the human being, is causally remarked upon and almost invisible. For the colonel Selva is a Tamil domestic servant – a structural element of his existence not a human being who has his own complete life. The dog is the final symbol of the colonel’s military mind-set (remnants of war) and of the inner demons he harbors within him, and after the dog has nearly taken the colonel’s life it dawns on him the fact that his current structure of existence does not let him become fully free and capable of seeing others as equally human as himself.   

   Professor Nussbaum is right in arguing that “compassion,” another term she uses to mean ethical sensibilities literature can develop, “requires one thing more: a sense of one’s own vulnerability to misfortune. To respond with compassion, I must be willing to entertain the thought that this suffering person might be me”(p. 91). Perhaps, this is not too far from one of the key ethical configurations in Buddhism: The theory of Karma, which is for me an ethical rationality more than a theory of causality.

 

  

  

 

 

 

 

 

   

 

 

 

  

 

No comments:

Post a Comment